Already have a subscription? Log in
That we might be the agents of our own extinction is a relatively recent idea in the story of the human species. As our understanding of our place within the cosmos has expanded, so too have the ethical demands placed upon us. During what could be the daybreak of human history, the severity of extinction rests on futures lost.
Text by Thomas Moynihan
Saint Augustine once wrote that the “world is like an oil press: under pressure”1 and listed the known calamities of his fourth-century world – “famine, war, want”. Today, 16 centuries later, we are more pressurised than before. We now know of many more worldly risks and our acquisition of knowledge, and power, has itself made more of them.
Writing in Roman North Africa at the opening of the Middle Ages, Augustine ultimately believed that history was a function of divine fulfilment. He compared the world to an oil press because he thought it was ineluctably sorting good souls from bad. He believed that, like the press, it would inevitably accomplish sorting and highest justice would be made consecrate, no matter what. The world may have been under pressure, but its future was secure.
We are now endowed with more history than Augustine. Burdened by centuries of accumulated knowing, we feel the pressure of the world in a completely different way. There is no security beyond our own actions. Our entire human future rests upon the deeds of today. Moreover, in our actions, the very future of human action itself is at stake. Especially now that we can enact our own destruction.
Historically speaking, it is perhaps shocking that humans have only very recently figured out that the human species could go extinct and, with it, everything humanly meaningful and valuable. This is not to say that humans are the only valuable things in the universe. Not at all. Rather, it is to say that we are the only beings (that we thus far know of) that can evaluate it, or, put a value on it.
But what is value? This remains an open question. But hereafter we mean it in its specifically moral sense: indexing our ability to regard certain states of affairs as morally “good” and imagine others as morally “better”. We navigate our world not just by talking about things, but by assessing them: venturing that some things ought to be and others ought not. Our language is not limited to what is or has been; it also enables us to resolve what should be.
Humans may not be the only valuable things, but are the only evaluators we know of. We are the only known beings capable of becoming responsive to the impartial demand to make the cosmos a better place for all, as well as recognise the capacity for good or bad in the consequences of our attempts to do so. As far as we know, no other beings can ethically improve themselves or their world, nor correct their beliefs about how best to do so.
In the West, people started worrying about human extinction sometime around 300 years ago, when poets and philosophers started anticipating visions of Earth’s biosphere continuing without us, bereft of all human concerns.
People have told stories about the end of all things since people first started telling stories. But the various apocalypses of religion and mythology invariably anticipate the end of the world as being inherently meaningful or moral, as somehow consummating meaning and justice within the universe, rather than irreversibly frustrating its realisation.
Moreover, none of the great apocalypses anticipate the extinguishment of value and meaning within a world that continues to exist, in its vast muteness and meaninglessness, totally devoid of humans or recognisably humane significances. Indeed, value and justice often were presumed to live on interminably in the spirits, the gods, or the afterlife.
So, the story goes something like this.
For most of Western history, value was invariably assumed indestructible in the sense that its aggregate remained constant and was conserved independently of human actions. This was the same whether this indestructibility was vouchsafed through belief in paternal deities or eternal returns of the same. Then, somewhere in the Enlightenment, when changes to material conditions became visible and the future came clearly into view as a target of meaningful moral influence, people realised value was mutable. It could be made or destroyed; it was capable of being consequentially diminished or augmented. But it was only recently that people awoke to the sheer breadth of potential future consequences – the sheer range for immense goodness or badness in outcomes.
During the Cold War, the collapse of Western civilisation, of global civilisation, and the termination of Homo sapiens were often spoken of interchangeably. There was little concerted effort to distinguish the severity of these outcomes and give a structure to the badness of global disaster.
Early glimmerings, however, are found back in 1958, when Bertrand Russell suggested that refusing a nuclear exchange, even if the price of pacificism was a global victory for despotic totalitarianism, remained vastly better than internecine annihilation. He urged that despotism was reversible, as were past “dark ages”, whereas outright extinction would be uniquely irreversible.2 To think otherwise, he suggested, is to sacrifice myopically the capacious opportunity of future generations for the narrow anxieties held by the present one (which may yet come to have seemed world-historically fleeting).
Some found the notion strange. Russell’s colleague in philosophy, Sidney Hook, swiftly replied in disagreement. He took issue with Russell’s suggestion of duty to the yet unborn and explained why:
I must confess that I have some difficulty with this notion of obligation, as if it implied there were millions of souls extending into eternity waiting to be born. I do not share this theology. If there are such souls, they may perhaps become embodied elsewhere. 3
But obligation to future generations is no theology. Absolving our duties to the future with the hopes that its promise and values will “become embodied elsewhere” – perhaps on planets further abroad – is actually itself much closer to theology. For it is to defer to the heavens, whether they are considered alien or angelic. Accountability to future generations is, in fact, theology’s opposite: the ultimate transposition of the locus of our ethics, of our responsibilities and their ramified pay-offs into the thoroughly secular – that is, worldly – arena of history.
Appropriately, “secular” originally meant “that which concerns the generations of humanity”.
1. Augustine, Sermones, xxiv.11.
2. B. Russell, ‘World Communism and Nuclear War’, New Leader, May 26 1958, pp. 9–12.
3. S. Hook, ‘A Free Man’s Choice’, New Leader, May 26 1958, pp. 9–12.
By the 1970s the murmurs were growing stronger. Here’s Estonian astronomer, Ernst Öpik, writing in 1973:
Compromise means trading the peaceful existence of yourself and your own generation against thousands of future generations which never will behold the light of day. 4
Öpik meant “compromise” in the negative sense: of compromising on one’s values. Our technical power outgrows our moral wisdom, so it becomes a race against time to shake off our moral immaturity before further technologies are invented that could immorally be misused to lock in an irreversibly bad outcome. “Compromise”, then, is not struggling right now to achieve temperance as a species. Deferring on this labour of self-improvement only means allowing more time for the juggernaut of civilisation to develop more technologies capable of being rashly used to foreclose such a victory.
As economist Robert L. Heilbroner pronounced a year later, the only hope for humanity rests “in our capacity to form a collective bond of identity with future generations”. 5
By 1983, Carl Sagan was insisting that, “if we are required to calibrate extinction in numerical terms, I would be sure to include the number of people in future generations who would not be born.” 6 Anti-nuclear campaigner Jonathan Schell had made a similar point the year before,7 noting that one of the apparent hallmarks of the human mind is an awareness of mortality. This has played an integral part in shaping the human soul since culture and language first evolved, but, within recent memory, our species has discovered a “second death”. A mortality yet more malign: the possibility for not just the individual, but the species, to perish.
Schell remarked that if humanity were wiped out, the mass causalities of current lives would represent the “first death”. But the worst causality, lurking behind the first, would be the “second death”: the loss of all future generations. Because the mind already staggers at the severity of the first, we tend to miss the far greater enormity of the second.
Perhaps the clearest statement came from philosopher Derek Parfit in 1984: “if we destroy mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think.” 8 To explain, he appealed to the reader to consider the distinctions in severity between:
1) peace2) a nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population3) a nuclear war that kills 100%.
We know 2) is worse than 1), and 3) worse than 2). But which is the greater difference? Parfit argued that it was between 3) and 2), not 2) and 1). He explained his reasoning:
Earth will remain inhabitable for at least another billion years. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history … If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second.
So, 2) would be immensely bad, but perhaps counterintuitively closer to 1) than it is to 3). Parfit argued that, if we do survive, there is scope for vast growth in the arts and sciences. Even more so, there is potential for progress in the youngest field of all: non-religious ethics. Parfit thought it was historically only very recently that people have started dedicating themselves to pursuing ethics focused exclusively on improving this secular world, and its future, rather than any perceived payoffs in some otherworldly beyond.
It is not just that the future could contain a vast amount of goodness as defined by today’s standards, it is also that it could contain forms of good and justice that are, as of now, entirely beyond our current conception. Perishing now would be forfeiting all this. It might be that even the greatest achievements of human civilisation so far represent only the foothills of our total potential: the pinnacles lie ahead in the mists of futurity.
4. E.J. Öpik, ‘Our Cosmic Destiny’, Irish Astronomical Journal, 11:4 (1973), pp. 121–22.5. R.L. Heilbroner, An Inquiry into The Human Prospect (London: Norton, 1975), p. 115.6. C. Sagan, ‘Nuclear War and Climatic Catastrophe: Some policy implications’, Foreign Affairs 62 (1983), pp. 257–292.7. J. Schell, The Fate of the Earth (New York: Knopf, 1982).8. D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: OUP, 1984).
Opposite, Close-up of solar eruption. Courtesy NASA/Goddard Space Flight Center
This attitude to the future is historically novel. Where prior generations, such as Augustine’s, thought we lived near the terminus of humanity’s mundane saga, many philosophers now believe we might be living at its daybreak. This is linked to the epoch-making discovery that value is made – that its subsistence is dependent upon our actions rather than maintained in independence of them – and, because it can be made, it can also be meaningfully lost. This defines the high-stakes attitude to history evinced above, from Russell to Parfit.
Against his belief that we stand at a bright new dawn for ethical reasoning and action, Parfit cited a competing notion: “Some people believe that there cannot be progress in Ethics, since everything has been already said.” This opinion, ironically or unironically, is nothing new. In around 350 BCE, Aristotle declared that “probably each art and science has often been developed as far as possible and has again perished”. This, he wrote, has happened “not once nor twice nor occasionally but infinitely often”. Therefore, within “the multitude of years … almost everything has been found out”. Inquiry and discovery are just remembering in the right way and trying to “supply defects” in our recall.9 This fits naturally with Plato’s own suggestion that knowledge is the remembrance of the lessons of past lives.
It was an almost universal conviction of the ancient world that all possibilities are eventually realised, or no possibility goes permanently unrealised. The realisation of nothing is forever frustrated. For millennia, contemplators were enamoured with the conviction that nature is as full of all possible things as it can be. There is no wasted opportunity: no place where some item could be, but simply never is; no gaps, no unoccupied real estate. This was a frequently unacknowledged assumption for large swathes of Western philosophy.
Of course, saying that no possibility goes permanently unrealised also means that no realisation can irreversibly return to the inexistence of mere possibility. This is one of the reasons why people didn’t apprehend the truth of permanent species extinctions – our own included – until very recently. It was thought that if a species was lost here and now, it would return some other place or at some other time.
So too, as Aristotle implied, with ideas and useful discoveries: if we forget some piece of knowledge, we can rest assured that it will one day be rediscovered. In this sense, knowledge can never be permanently forgotten. Whatever is lost will return; discovery is just remembering the past.
So too with moral value: if all valuable things and events are reliably and inevitably realised – entirely independently of our actions – then we cannot change or influence that aggregate amount. The best we can do, given Aristotle’s belief that everything valuable has already been somewhere discovered, is understand “maximising value” as nothing more than the task of returning to elder maxima. This implies an indestructibility of value: it cannot be created.
The indestructibility of value means that value is conserved through all its destructions and generations. The total amount never changes, even if local quantity is subject to shifts. Value is never globally diminished or grown, it is transferred elsewhere in time or space. We cannot leverage meaningful change upon the amount in the world. We can perfect ourselves, becoming more virtuous, but this is a personal and parochial affair, never one that transforms material conditions globally and irreversibly. There is therefore no meaningful historical change. Indeed, perfecting ourselves is revisiting previous peaks of virtuosity, following prior example and fulfilling well-established natural ends, rather than searching for forms of perfection as-yet-unrealised.
9. Aristotle, Complete Works: Revised Oxford Translations, ed. J. Barnes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1698 and 2005) vol.1 556, vol.2.
Background belief in an indestructibility of value persisted, from the eternal returns of the Greeks into the hopeful eschatology of Christianity. For medieval Christendom, humans may have blighted creation, bringing in imperfection through misused freedom, but, in the end, this is just a blip, the interval of worldly history just a detour within an otherwise insoluble consummation of divine justice.
As Augustine wrote, the “goodness” of created beings “can be augmented and diminished”, 10 but, ultimately, “all natures are good, because their author is supremely good”. Variability is just an illusion, caused by limited perspective: “variable good was created and is governed alone by the immutable good.” 11
Here Augustine was practising something we now call theodicy – justifying the ways of God to man, rationalising the ways things are. The theodicean impulse rests in the desire to believe that value and justice are not dependent on our actions but are perfectly maintained, like permanent natural constants, independently of our deeds.
For both the ancient Greek and medieval Christian, individuals could create local fluctuations, but the global amount of good could not be meaningfully diminished nor augmented by humans. Assuming value immutable, you are never going to answer the demands of protecting or promoting it.
This is not to say that people of these past eras were carefree or insouciant. When it came to personal affairs, they were surely as motivated and concerned as we are today. Probably they were often more wise, virtuous and upright. But there could yet be little sense of a humanmade future within which there is radically more, or less, goodness than today.
Assurance in value’s indestructibility persisted well into the modern epoch, perpetuating itself into the scientific worldview. In the wake of the scientific revolution, the riddle of “evil” or “corruption” gained new resonance. Looking down telescopes in the early 1600s, pioneers like Galileo noticed that the heavens – which the ancients and medievals presumed to be perfect and incorruptible – were themselves subject to decay and destruction. Sunspots were noticed. This implied that suns themselves die, which, in turn implied the mortality of entire solar systems. How could a perfect creation, designed by the perfect creator, admit to such imprudent squander?
The recourse was indestructible value. Many scientists and naturalists during the early modern epoch simply claimed that for every sun that dies, another is necessarily born. This was thought to apply also to populated worlds. Moreover, it was often applied to the species that inhabit them. It was numerously argued that if a species dies on one planet, it will re-emerge on another in the fullness of time. Because of this, the destruction of planet Earth would only be a temporary setback for an eternally recurring humanity.
For example, in 1686, the French writer Bernard Fontenelle pronounced with confidence that for all the “ancient Stars that disappear, other new ones are born in their places, and that Defect in Nature must [be] repair’d”. He concluded that this meant the true extinction, of any natural “Species”, was impossible.
What should appear as the extinction of value and life – instanced in the destruction of populous planets – was explained away as just the cosmic circulation of these things. (The same, of course, applies to their generation.) If we could see the whole, we would know that all remains balanced. Writers from the 1600s to 1800s were enthralled by this theodicy-derived excuse to ignore the observational evidence of a physical universe imprudently dying for no reason whatsoever.
10. Augustine, Enchiridion, Caput 12.
11. Augustine, Contra aduersarium legis et prophetarum, Book 1, Caput 6.
Pablo Carlos Budassi, Observable universe logarithmic illustration, under a CC license
The intuition that all achievable glories lay in the fullness of the past, rather than in the pregnancy of the future, also persisted stubbornly. Romantic poets of the early 1800s, struck by the ballooning age of the Earth as revealed by geology, could not help but dream that the prehistoric expanses of time were full of unknown civilisations 12 – each of which may have reached the apex of art, civics and virtue.
But another vision had been brewing through the later 1700s. Coupled with the Industrial Revolution and the Enlightenment, it rested in the recognition that value (whatever it may ultimately be) is something artfully made by humans, and is somehow dependent on our activity, rather than given to us by nature. With this, came the conjoint insight that value is mutable. That it can be maximised or minimised, frustrated or consummated, augmented or destroyed, all dependent upon our actions. We can’t simply rest assured that all useful knowledge will be rediscovered or that the desecration of every populated planet is compensated by another’s birth.
The mutability of value is a recognition at the heart of the modern world. It stands at the root of modernity’s two major moral systems, both appearing during the 1700s: deontology and utilitarianism. Deontologist Immanuel Kant said that there “remains, then, nothing but the value which we ourselves give our life”, 13 and the only way to live up to this recognition is to follow it in a maximal sense. We must treat justice – or the treating of each other as fully autonomous evaluators – as if this were a law of nature. Kant saw that this ideal was very imperfectly realised at present, and so argued its maximal realisation was a goal to be achieved throughout humanity’s future. He argued that an ultimate moral crime would be failing to advance this end: the mere “maintenance of humanity” is not good enough; realising our potential for “greater perfection” is also obligatory. 14
For utilitarianism, the compulsion to maximisation is even clearer. It wasn’t long before consequentialists were talking about the “quantum” of goodness as assessed from “the point of view of the universe”, 15 in the words of Henry Sidgwick from the 1890s, or defining “right” as that which increases “the total goodness of the universe”, as G.E. Moore ventured in 1903. 16
With this came a new sense that we could affect the future and the amount of value in it. Here lies modernity’s preference for futurity’s open-ended opportunity over the past’s precedential straitjacket. Sidgwick, at the close of the 1800s, was already assessing the “interests of posterity” and pronouncing that someone’s placement within time cannot affect our evaluation of them. But this means we have obligations to the future, because our actions in the present can significantly affect “the number of future human (or sentient) beings”. At the extreme, we must “even” consider as variable the very “existence of human beings to be affected”. Indeed, as early as 1874, Sidgwick had realised that – based on the potential future value lost – allowing human extinction “would be the greatest of conceivable crimes from a Utilitarian point of view”. 17
Yet earlier, Kant had acknowledged that the future fulfilment of humanity’s “progress towards the better” could be fatally frustrated. He worried about some catastrophe “which will push aside the human species”. Just how bad would such an outcome be? For Kant, this wasted opportunity for progress and growth would be the worst of all losses. Without humans, he wrote, “the whole creation would be a mere waste, in vain, and without a final purpose”. This is not to argue that creation was created for rational beings (as the theodicean would say), but that, without rational beings, there would be no agents to work towards giving a reason to the arbitrariness of nature.
12. P.B. Shelley, Letters, ed. F.L. Jones (Oxford: OUP, 1964), 1:189.
13. I. Kant, Critique of Judgement (New York: Dover, 2005), p. 212.
14. I. Kant, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals (New York: Dover, 2005), p. 48.
15. H. Sidgwick, Methods in Ethics (London, 1907).
16. G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Oxford: OUP, 1903), p. 89.
17. H. Sidgwick, Methods in Ethics (London, 1874).
Having woken up to the fact that the universe was not designed for the immutable benefit of evaluating beings, and that value is therefore mutable within it, it quickly became clear that humans could, across future history, effect consequential change upon the “good” in the world.
But, by the turn of the 1900s, many people were waking up to the fundamental fact that all valuable things (whatever they might be) require energy. People were starting to acknowledge that almost all complex systems – from ecosystems to sentient brains to civilisation itself – run entirely on translated sunlight.
Given advancement of knowledge far beyond the early modern observation of sunspots, scientists had, since the birth of thermodynamics in the mid-1800s, been attempting to accurately estimate our sun’s continued lifetime. And where previously the death of our sun would have been cheerily justified (in the mode of theodicy) by belief in the compensatory birth of another sun (and Earth) elsewhere, this was no longer believable.
Why? Because, in 1865, German mathematician and physicist Rudolf Clausius announced “entropy”. Thermodynamics showed that while energy is conserved over time, the amount of useful energy is irreversibly running down. Entropy is the recognition that all change requires disbalance and our cosmos is tending towards balance and so universal stasis. Clausius concluded, once and for all, that our universe does not go in “never-ending cycles” of destruction and renewal, but tends towards a “state of unchanging death” where “no further change can ever more take place”. 18
Not long after, in 1900, Nikola Tesla declared that the “great problem of science” is harnessing more of the sun’s energy. The reason why no one had previously articulated this “great problem” before Tesla’s generation was because they frequently assumed useful energy cosmically unlimited and indestructible. They didn’t acknowledge that, in cosmic timescales, it is scarce.
But Clausius’ entropy revealed an insuperable cosmic budget of value creation, here and everywhere, forever. The endowment may be gargantuan, but it is finite. Suns may perish and others be born, but over time the direction of travel is toward universal caput mortuum. There could now no longer be any serious belief that the good – reliant as it is, whatever it is, upon energy – remains eternally indestructible.
Some reacted with dejection and disillusion. Historian Henry Adams prophesied that the “final equilibrium” means humanity can only “look forward only to a diversified agony” without “hope of escaping imbecility”. 19 Yet precisely because there was an ultimately finite amount of resource and time available with which to channel it toward valuable things, it suddenly became possible to have a meaningful impact upon the total amount of good that will be eventually realised. It is in fact the elder belief in an eternal reservoir of unlimited energy and value that makes our actions and works meaningless and trivial. The exculpations of eternity are intoxicating. Against the hasty pessimism of Adams, then, it is the ultimate scarcity of potential goodness that makes maximising it meaningful.
The amount of time left was swiftly calculated to be stupendous. In 1929, physicist James Jeans calculated that “earth is likely to remain a possible abode of life for something of the order of a million million years to come”.20 We are thus potentially standing “at the first flush of the dawn of civilization”. 21
Jeans had a remarkable way of envisioning this: imagine stacking a postage stamp on a penny, and then balancing both upon the pinnacle of a 20-metre-high obelisk. The thickness of the stamp is the extent of recorded history, the thickness of the stamp and penny is the extent of our species’ existence, and the distance from the stamp to the obelisk’s base is the age of our Earth. He went on:
Now stick another postage-stamp on top of the first to represent the next 5000 years of civilization, and keep sticking on postage-stamps until you have a pile as high as Mont Blanc … The first postage-stamp was the past of civilization; the column higher than Mont Blanc its future. Or, to look at it in another way, the first postage-stamp represents what man has already achieved; the pile which out-tops Mont Blanc represents what he may achieve.
Of course, “accidents may happen” to the species. Jeans listed the calamities known in the early 1900s, from “celestial collisions” to solar explosions:
Accident may replace our Mont Blanc of postage-stamps by a truncated column of only a fraction of the height of Mont Blanc. Even so, there is prospect of tens of thousands of millions of years before our race … We have come into being in the fresh glory of the dawn, and a day of almost unthinkable length stretches before us with unimaginable opportunities for accomplishment … We are still too much engulfed in the greyness of the morning mists to be able to imagine, however vaguely, how this world of ours will appear to those who will come after us and see it in the full light of day. But by what light we have, we seem to discern that the main message [is] one of responsibility: of responsibility because we are drawing plans and laying foundations for a longer future than we can well imagine.
The preponderance of achievement lies in a future pregnant with possibility, rather than within the already realised wisdom of the past – the perfect inversion of the ancient Greek attitude.
In 1935, the historian Arnold J. Toynbee pointed exactly this out.22 He explained that with the help of modern knowledge – from palaeoanthropology to the aging of the Earth – we can now refute the “brilliant conjectures” of Plato and Aristotle and their speculations upon a past immensity pregnant filled with forgotten wonders. In neat reversal, the expanse of achievement and greatness lies ahead. Toynbee calculated that given the number of civilisations humanity had created in the 6,000 years since they first emerged, Jeans’ prospect affords us a further 1,743,000,000 civilisational lifespans yet to come before the sun renders Earth uninhabitable.
18. R. Clausius, ‘On the Second Fundamental Theorem of the Mechanical Theory of Heat’, Philosophical Magazine 35 (1868), pp. 417–19.
19. H. Adams, The Tendency of History (New York: 1929), p. 48.
20. J. Jeans, The Universe Around Us (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1929), p. 352.
21. J. Jeans, Eos: Or, the Wider Aspects of Cosmogony (London: Kegan Paul, 1928), pp. 12–13, 83–84.
22. A.J. Toynbee, A Study of History: Volume 1, The Geneses of Civilizations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1935), p. 173, 460–63.
If sunlight is gradually running out, every wasted ray is a wasted opportunity and so no longer morally neutral. Some, again in a mode of nihilistic disillusion, took this lesson of solar inefficiency as a recommendation to action. French philosopher Georges Bataille commended orgiastic waste, over and above accumulated “utility”, as a means for us to recapitulate the “full rapture of those great swarms of stars”, by re-enacting – in microcosm – their “violent expenditure of self” by communally breathing “in the power of death”. 23
But, just as much as the elder theodicy, this remains beholden to the naive notion that nature dictates moral lessons to us. Nature owes us nothing, but neither does it command or exact anything from us. The loss of theodicy’s conviction that nature is inherently prudent is not an enjoinder for imprudence on our part. It merely amounts to the lesson that the legitimacy of prudence, as moral standard, does not derive from nature’s precedent but from our own legislation. If we ever want anything other than waste and wasted opportunity as the default of this lavishly dying cosmos, we will have to forge it ourselves.
And so, others instead set to work proposing ways to engineer a fix for solar inefficiency and the cap that it sets upon value creation. By the late 1920s, the Irish scientist J.D. Bernal was contemplating the fact that on Earth, “even if we should use all the solar energy which we receive we should still be wasting all but one two billionths of the energy that the sun gives out”. He suggested a grandiose solution to such inefficiency: manufacture a giant artificial sphere around the sun, to soak up every drop of its outgoing energy, channelling energetic waste to valuable purpose. Such a project may seem like science fiction, but scientists today continue to endorse its plausibility.
It wasn’t long until others were imagining such an extraction of resource – a harvesting of goodness from the cosmic cataract of entropy – at a galactic scale. In a 1930 novel, Olaf Stapledon rhapsodically envisioned a Milky Way wherein every solar system was “surrounded by a gauze of light traps, which focused the escaping solar energy for intelligent use”.24 A galaxy made artful and purposeful, rather than a whorl of luxuriant waste; a spiral of stars irrigated and awoken to the fruitfulness of life, rather than left to generate and extinguish it randomly and accidentally.
A far cry from Aristotle’s conviction that everything achievable has happened in the past, here is a vision of a future where agents reroute nature’s squander towards valuable pursuits – whether these be art, industry, or cogitation itself – at such a grand scale that even the purposeless squanders of the past, though remaining forever unjustified, may begin to look less cruel. It’s the closest thing intelligence will get to theodicy in a godless world: and it will only happen if we make it ourselves.
So, the story goes something like this.
First, there was a comforting sense that justice was upheld by nature independently of us, that value was indestructible. Then, we lost this security, realising that value is ultimately destructible. Some reacted – and still continue to react – with a form of dejected disillusion: thinking that this means we can do away with chimerical notions of justice and value since we cannot find them reflected back to us by the cosmos. But this still is to believe that we can only follow nature’s precedent, benevolent or wanton. This is not so. As with art, we forge value ourselves.
Recognising that value is made means recognising that it can be minimised or maximised. Acknowledging this is answering the demand to maximise it fully. The destructibility of value enjoins its maximisation. Now that we have some grasp of the ultimate constraints on this – of the cosmic endowments of time and energy – we have some sense of what might truly be at stake. Let’s hope we can handle the pressure. ◉
23. G. Bataille, ‘Celestial Bodies’, October 36 (1986), pp. 75–78.
24. O. Stapledon, Last and First Men/Star Maker (New York: Dover, 1968).
Kevin Gill, 3D rendering of a Dyson sphere utilizing large, orbiting panels, under a CC license